Thursday, January 31, 2008

Decomposing Descriptive Content

I think that descriptivists may have to reject semantic compositionality in some cases. In particular, the two sentences (1) 'Bob is human' and (2) 'Bob = Bob' may not be strictly decomposable in their descriptive contents. I will show that there is another term X which can replace the first mention of 'Bob' in the first sentence, but not in the second, without altering the sentence's content. So the contribution that either term ('Bob' or X) makes to the meaning of the whole depends on the rest of the sentence in which it is embedded. In sentence #1, 'Bob' and X will contribute the same semantic value, whereas in sentence #2 they will differ.

First, some background: I use 'descriptive content' to refer to the kind of ('narrow') representational content or semantic value that is grounded in scenarios (conceptual possibilities, or centered possible worlds considered as actual) -- namely, the primary intension. For example, the descriptive content of a proper name, 'Bob', is given by some associated reference-fixing descriptive property, D, such that 'Bob = the D' is analytic (if D can be captured in our language). Equivalently: it is the set of possible persons who are such that he is Bob follows a priori from the hypothesis that his world is actual. [Read up on the links if this is hard to follow.]

Now for the argument:

Consider a perfectly symmetrical universe, containing two qualitative duplicates we may dub 'Bob' and 'Mirror-Bob'. They share all their objective intrinsic and extrinsic properties (for their surroundings are also qualitatively identical). So there is no difference between them -- no unique property that could fix the reference of my term 'Bob' (or 'Mirror-Bob') as referring to the one person rather than the other.* Probably the best way to make sense of this is to say that the two terms are indeterminate between the two referents, and so to assess the truth of any sentence involving the terms, we supervaluate over the various possibilities.
* = Aside: this problem could be overcome if we were inside this universe, for then we could appeal to the relative property of being the Bob in my vicinity, or whatever.

Consider, then, the following sentences:
(1) 'Bob is human' and (2) 'Bob = Bob'

And compare the first-term substitutions:
(1a) 'Mirror-Bob is human' and (2a) 'Mirror-Bob = Bob'

Both 1 and 1a are true, and indeed true in all the same scenarios, which is to say that they have the same descriptive content. (Intuitively: to say that Bob is human, and to say that Mirror-Bob is human, is not to describe two different scenarios. Both names actually range indeterminately over the same two people, and both apply equally determinately to any unique Bob-counterparts in other, non-symmetric, worlds.)

But 2 and 2a clearly differ in content, for the former is true and the latter false! For although it is indeterminate which of the two people each of these terms denotes, it is determinate that they denote numerically distinct people. (Either 'Bob' denotes the one guy and 'Mirror-Bob' the other, or vice versa. On either way of resolving the indeterminacy, the names turn out not to be co-referential. Hence, by supervaluation, it is determinate that they are non-co-referential.)

The problem for compositionality is that this fact -- that the two terms do not co-refer -- cannot be derived from the descriptive contents of each term alone. Indeed, we've seen that both names have the same primary intension (an intension which happens to be indeterminate at this world, but not at others). But, despite having the same content, they can potentially make significantly different contributions to the content of a whole sentence in which they are part, as the comparison of 2 with 2a shows.

(Can anyone suggest a neater way to make sense of this puzzle case?)

3 comments:

  1. (I'm not entirely up on this stuff, so please excuse me if I employ some terms the wrong way; hopefully my point will be clear nonetheless)

    "no[thing] could fix the reference of my term 'Bob' (or 'Mirror-Bob') as referring to the one person rather than the other"

    "although it is indeterminate which of the two people each of these terms denotes, it is determinate that they denote numerically distinct people. (Either 'Bob' denotes the one guy and 'Mirror-Bob' the other, or vice versa."

    This is the move that lost me. I took the first paragraph as stating that each term had a non-determinate referent. But the second claims that they do have some determinate referent, but it's indeterminate which it is.

    Those claims sound contradictory to me, and it also sounds as though the first is by far more plausible. But if that's true then 2a can be true - it states that each of two indeterminate names is indeterminate between the same referents.

    (Though does it also make 1 and 1a false? You can't state of an indeterminate entity that it is human, though I suspect that I've misunderstood here)

    ReplyDelete
  2. Interesting. I don't think the puzzle has much to do with descriptivism, though. The worry arises equally for theories according to which meaning is reference. The referential semantic value of the two terms is presumably the same (divided between the two individuals), but the truth-value of the two sentences is different.

    Of course it's easy to see what's going on once we supervaluate: each precisification behaves compositionally, but the precisification of the terms must be constrained so that each term has different referent on each precisification. This constraint doesn't supervene on the divided reference (or intension) of each term alone, hence the worry for compositionality of the supervaluation as a whole. One could get around this by allowing relations such as difference of reference into semantic value, as on Kit Fine's semantic relationism (but of course this goes beyond standard referentialism and descriptivism).

    Incidentally the same issue arises with i and -i, the two square roots of -1.

    ReplyDelete
  3. djc - thanks! I guess you're right about the generality of the puzzle; I just found it easier to spell out assuming descriptivism. "i and -i" is a neat example. I'll need to look into Fine's stuff.

    Alex - See my follow-up post: The Logic of Indeterminacy.

    ReplyDelete

Visitors: check my comments policy first.
Non-Blogger users: If the comment form isn't working for you, email me your comment and I can post it on your behalf. (If your comment is too long, first try breaking it into two parts.)

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.