There seems to be a distinction between 'descriptive' and 'evaluative' meanings of sentences. Descriptive meanings are cognitive (have truth values) and express propositions. It might be suggested that evaluative meanings are non-cognitive, expressing attitudes instead. Some statements might be purely descriptive, such as "Pandas are animals." Other utterances seem purely evaluative, e.g. "Hooray for philosophy!" Consider the phrase: "These are good scissors," which most clearly expresses a positive evaluation of the scissors. The phrase also seems to involve a descriptive component, i.e. that the scissors are sharp and able to cut well, or something along those lines. ("Good" is rather generic - the descriptive meaning more obvious in the case of more specific evaluative terms such as "intelligent", "courageous", etc.)
What is the relationship between descriptive and evaluative meaning? Non-cognitivists will want to say that the two are entirely distinct, mirroring the fact-value distinction. Moral realists will suggest that there is only one type of meaning (descriptive meaning), though of course language can be employed for a variety of purposes. As a reductionist, I will argue that evaluative meanings are contained within the broader category of descriptive meanings.
I think a desire-based analysis of value (where we take "good" to mean "is such to fulfill the relevant desires") offers a neat explanation of the link between descriptive and evaluative meanings. "These scissors are good" (value) just means "these scissors will fulfill the relevant desires" (fact). To fill in the details: we all recognise that people usually want scissors for cutting stuff. We know that to best fulfill these desires, the scissors should be sharp. So, in the appropriate contexts, we can infer "these scissors are sharp" from "these scissors are good". The descriptive meaning follows from the evaluative meaning, for they are really just one and the same.
It's not clear to me that the non-cognitivist can so readily explain this connection. They hold facts and values to be entirely separate spheres, such that no descriptive facts can entail an evaluative conclusion. So you should, in principle, be able to couple a positive evaluation with any descriptive claim whatsoever. This disallows the sort of reasoning (from one 'type' of meaning to another) demonstrated in the previous paragraph. For example, the non-cognitivist might agree that the scissors are sharp and so would best fulfill our 'cutting' desires, yet disagree that the scissors are in any way "good". This strikes me as inconsistent.
Now, it's true that someone might admit the scissors to be good for our purposes, yet still hold a negative attitude towards them himself. This suggests to me that we need to distinguish between evaluations and attitudes. Evaluations are made objectively, relative to some set of standards. Attitudes are purely subjective - expressions of personal whim rather than real value. So my understanding of 'evaluative meaning' is actually quite different from that initially described in this post. Utterances like "philosophy rules!" express positive attitudes, but have no real evaluative meaning, since it isn't made clear just what the value of philosophy is. (Compare this to "philosophy develops the mind", which makes a descriptive claim about what good it is that philosophy does, and thus could be said to have genuine evaluative meaning.)
So, all meaning is descriptive meaning. Evaluative meaning is just a particular kind of descriptive meaning, namely, the kind concerned with facts about desire fulfillment (or whatever the natural 'reduction basis' for value turns out to be). Value claims are about desires, and thus are cognitive. Expressions of attitude are something else entirely, distinct from the value claims involved in typical evaluative terms like 'good', 'intelligent', etc. The non-cognitivist is mistaken to conflate these.
But we might now instead consider the "meaning/attitude distinction". This looks similar to how the non-cognitivist originally conceived the descriptive/evaluative distinction, except that value is now located in the left box. We can safely agree with the non-cognitivist that this is a strict distinction, for it is also a fairly unimportant one. It no longer allows the non-cognitivist to insist that descriptive premises cannot yield evaluative conclusions, for instance. The analogous claim that meanings cannot yield attitudes seems far less threatening.
Saturday, March 05, 2005
6 comments:
Visitors: check my comments policy first.
Non-Blogger users: If the comment form isn't working for you, email me your comment and I can post it on your behalf. (If your comment is too long, first try breaking it into two parts.)
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Richard,
ReplyDelete"For example, the non-cognitivist might agree that the scissors are sharp and so would best fulfill our 'cutting' desires, yet disagree that the scissors are in any way "good". This strikes me as inconsistent."
The non-cognitivist can say that the scissors are good, because they fulfill the relevant desires. In order to do this, they have to also feel that cutting is good.. or at least that fulfilling the cutting desire is good. Of course, good doesn't mean quite the same thing... all it really is is approval - or an evaluation.
Consider the analogous case involving a gun. Is the gun good or not? Is it good if it fulfills the relevant desire - that is, killing things? What if I don't value killing things? Perhaps it is good qua a gun. However, is it morally good? This seems to depend on your value web.
When you say "it is a good pair of scissors", the non-cognitivist would say that you are making both a descriptive claim and an evaluative claim. The scissors are an aid to cutting things. We both agree that that is descriptive. But where I disagree is that the decision of "relevant desires" is itself an evaluation. I may say the relevant desires to be fulfilled for a pair of scissors is cutting paper, you may want them to be able to cut cans. Similarly, a "good wife" may be submissive, quiet, and tidy to me, and supportive, independent, and intelligent to you. In saying that something is good, we describe and evaluate. With the scissors example, people will usually agree, but agreement seems to be a dangerous premise to base moral truth on.
Also, 'good' seems to have its own problems, separate from the reductionist/non-cognitivist debate. Lets look at another word, say, pious. It reduces perfectly down to a descriptive claim - "devoutly religious". However, I don't feel confident that I convince someone to join the church, without the evaluative content - namely "Hurrah for Pious!" This evaluative content may reduce down to preference satisfaction - perhaps it is actually false that piety maximises preference satisfaction, and it is by convincing you that this is the case, and ultimately appealing to the fact that you value preference satisfaction, that I bring you around to disliking piety (or dogmatism, if you will :)).
It seems to me that I haven't done anything to 'prove' non-cognitivism, or even refute your theory. I guess, in one sense, it is tautologically true that individual preference satisfaction is morality, but how strong is that truth? It doesn't seem to imply very much, and I'm not actually sure whether preference satisfaction doesn't reduce down to getting what you want. Yet this doesn't say anything about what others want, and how to aggregate the wants of others to get an overall morality. I don't value other people getting what they want just because they want it: I want people to want certain things too. Whats more, some people probably want people to have their desires thwarted (hehe lets not get onto that topic :)) ! Perhaps individual preference satisfaction is important to basically everybody, merely because it would be logically possible to want something, and not want to have something come to be the case.
Is your theory any different to non-cognitivism? If so, where exactly is that difference? Is it because you take the further step of combining everybody's desires into a larger morality? Or is it simply a terminology thing?
Once again, I've confused myself. Please clarify things for me - I'm finding it pretty hard to do it for myself at this point! :)
Yeah, I should clarify that in this post I really wasn't discussing morality at all, but just value generally.
ReplyDeleteI agree that the 'relevant desires' will vary according to context, and something can have a form of value (e.g. a 'good' gun) whilst being morally bad, or able to be put to bad purposes, or whatever.
Part of the point I'm trying to make is that evaluations can be made relative to some standard that is not individually subjective. (Though of course whether someone cares about this standard will vary from person to person.) We can judge the gun to be 'good qua gun' even if we personally disapprove of firearms. So the non-cognitivist seems mistaken in relating all value judgments to subjective attitudes. (If that is indeed what NC does - I may be misrepresenting the position?) Attitudes and evaluations are not the same thing.
This difference is particularly important in the case of morality, where, as you note, I "take the further step of combining everybody's desires". But the difference starts even before this. The initial difference, I think, comes from recognising that evaluations are not expressing attitudes ("hooray!", etc.), but are instead 'cognitive' in that they make propositional claims about desires ("X will fulfill desire Y" is either true or false). Attitudes are something distinct from objective evaluation.
I'm a little confused about some of the main post myself actually, but does this make any more sense?
I think I see where we differ on this. "X will fulfill desire Y" is definately a description, but it is strictly not an evaluation, at least not the way the non-cognitivist means evaluation. The evaluation is the implied "and hurrah for that!"
ReplyDeleteNot quite - recall that I want to distinguish evaluation from attitude. We can evaluate something as a 'good gun' without any accompanying 'hurrahs' at all.
ReplyDeleteTo make the descriptive statement: "X will fulfill desire Y", is (I argue) to evaluate X with respect to Y. Evaluations are just a sort of description, in that way. Whether or not we personally approve of X and Y, however, is an entirely separate question. That's where attitudes come in.
(I suspect our disagreement stems from using the word 'evaluation' to mean different things?)
For the sake of the argument, I will use your definition of evaluation. Those kinds of descriptions that attribute (certain kinds of?)qualities. Attidudes are exactly the same as what the non-cognitivists would call evaluations. Structurally, it still seems to be the same situation. Surely attitudes can fulfil the same roles as the old evaluations could?
ReplyDeleteThe non-cognitivist would argue, that moral philsophy is a normative philosophy, and in order to recommend action, some kind of attitude must be invoked. Even if I manage to argue that, say, free tertiary education, increases the preference fulfillment of everyone, I cannot conclude that the government should support it. In order for the government to support it, they would have to have a positive attitude towards fulfilling everyones preferences. They may prefer to fulfill all of their own preferences, at the cost of everyone else's happiness.
What I am saying, is that at the basis for any moral judgement, is an attitude. We can all have the same attitude toward some moral judgement, but that doesn't make it true, because it is still contingently possible to disagree with the majority, and there is no external system to recommend one attitude over the other.
at least, this is what the non-cognitivist would say. Of course, you could insist that there is an objective moral truth. If the truths are contained within us, however, they seem to still rely, ultimately, upon our attitudes. And whats the truth when two people disagree?
Amoralistic psychopaths can conduct moral reasoning and make moral judgments. This sinks non-cognitivism. The non-cognitivist can claim that it's only "as if" they conduct moral reasoning, but that's just hand-waving.
ReplyDeleteWhen two people disagree, truth is relativised. As the story may get more complicated by a rebuttal to that, see my J. of Social Phil. article of 2003, "Moral Relativism and the Argument from Disagreement," which I think puts the old issue to rest.