Tuesday, September 18, 2007

The Maxim of Mirroring

Jonathan Ichikawa discusses a curious puzzle, 'It must be so (but I wouldn’t say that it is so)':
“it must be that X” can be [used] to express high confidence in X. What’s striking me is that this is so even when, intuitively, my epistemic position isn’t strong enough to just assert X. Is that weird? ...

I know that sometimes, pragmatic rules prohibit me from asserting things that are entailed by other things that I can assert, like when I say “she’s more than four feet tall” when someone asks me how tall she is and I know that she’s 5′4″. But this seems worse: I’m prohibited by something like the maxim of quality from asserting something that is strictly stronger than something I am permitted to assert.

This strikes me as a special use of the modal 'must'. In saying, "it must be that X", we are not merely communicating the claim "it is the case that X" with additional modal force ("it is - indeed, must be - the case that X"). Rather, we seem to be saying something more like, "General considerations force me to conclude that X." We are indicating a certain indirectness of thought; a need for inference from the general to the specific. That is how we reached the conclusion ourselves, after all. By forcing the listener to undergo a similar process, we communicate that this is how we reached the conclusion ourselves. (We may need to add this "maxim of mirroring" to Grice's list!)

On this account, then, direct assertion ("X is the case") implicates possession of direct evidence. Note that introducing the 'must' - though semantically stronger - requires us to make an inferential step before we reach the simple conclusion that X is the case. By drawing out the listener's thoughts in this roundabout way, one mirrors the thoughts of the speaker. That is, you communicate that your grounds for believing X are indirect (and so perhaps insufficient for knowledge). In this way, it can be felicitous to make the strong claim "X must be the case" - even if you lack sufficient evidence for the weaker claim that X is actually true.

A problem remains. Suppose you don't know whether X is true, but may permissibly say 'it must be that X.' Assuming that knowledge is the norm of assertion, Jonathan points out that we must either (1) deny that 'it must be that X' entails X on the above use of 'must', or (2) claim that 'it must be that X' is not an assertion but "some more tentative thing." (I guess a third option would be to deny that knowledge is closed over entailment.) Which of these options most naturally fits the story I've told above?

4 comments:

  1. This reminds me of a linguistics course I took. You might find the wikipedia article on "linguistic modality" interesting, especially the part on epistemic modality. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Linguistic_modality#Epistemic_moods

    ReplyDelete
  2. A or B or C or D (as in a multiple choice question). Then we assert '-A & -C & -D' but we have no idea about C. Then 'It must be C'.

    But can we ever get to 'It must be that C' (in the sense where it is weaker than 'C') without this finite range of options?

    Of course, in the multiple choice case we have 'a xor b xor c xor d', so 'it must be C' really does entail 'C', so the original intuition is simply mistaken. Perhaps we have a proposition coupled with an expression:

    'It must be the case that X' translates to 'X, {nervous frown}'.

    ReplyDelete
  3. whoops, that should have been '-A and -B and - D' in the prev. comment.

    ReplyDelete
  4. "By forcing the listener to undergo a similar process, we communicate that this is how we reached the conclusion ourselves. (We may need to add this "maxim of mirroring" to Grice's list!)"

    Nay, I think a decalogue is more than enough!

    But in my PhD dissertation, I did dwell at large in this mirroring effect, as you call it.

    Later, I found French author Daellenbach had called it "speculatory" which has a nice Latin touch to it!

    For Grice it's what Apel (wrongly) calls "strategical": it's instrumental rationality when you manipulate an object: it's strategic when it's communicative: when your co-object is a person! Etc.

    J. L. Speranza
    for the GriceClub.blogspot
    jlsperanza@aol.com

    ReplyDelete

Visitors: check my comments policy first.
Non-Blogger users: If the comment form isn't working for you, email me your comment and I can post it on your behalf. (If your comment is too long, first try breaking it into two parts.)

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.